• 数学世纪


    The
    Mathematical
    Century
    The
    30 Greatest
    Problems
    of tre
    Last 1 00 Years

    At the beginning of the seventeenth century, two great philosophers,
    Francis Bacon in England and Rene Descartes in France, proclaimed
    the birth of modern science. Each of them described his vision of
    the future. Their visions were very different.
    Bacon said, "All depends on keeping the eye steadily fixed on the
    facts of nature. " Descartes said, "I think, therefore I am."
    According to Bacon, scientists should travel over the
    earth collecting facts, until the accumulated facts reveal how
    Nature works. The scientists will then induce from the facts
    the laws that Nature obeys. According to Descartes, scientists
    should stay at home and deduce the laws of Nature by pure
    thought. In order to deduce the laws correctly, the scientists
    will need only the rules oflogic and knowledge of the existence
    of God. For four hundred years since Bacon and Descartes led
    the way, science has raced ahead by following both paths simultaneously.
    Neither Baconian empiricism nor Cartesian dogmatism has the power
    to elucidate Nature's secrets by itself, but both together have been
    amazingly successful. For four hundred years,
    English scientists have tended to be Baconian and
    French scientists Cartesian.

     

    Faraday and Darwin and Rutherford were Baconians: Pascal
    and Laplace and Poincare were Cartesians. Science was greatly
    enriched by the cross-fertilization of the two contrasting national
    cultures. Both cultures were always at work in both countries.
    Newton was at heart a Cartesian, using pure thought as Descartes
    intended, and using it to demolish the Cartesian dogma of vortices.
    Marie Curie was at heart a Baconian, boiling tons of crude uranium
    ore to demolish the dogma of the indestructibility of atoms.

    Piergiorgio Odifreddi has done a superb job, telling the
    story of twentieth-century mathematics in one short and readable volume.
    My only complaint about this book is that Piergiorgio's account is a
    little too Cartesian for my taste. It presents
    the history of mathematics as more orderly and logical than I
    imagine it. I happen to be a Baconian while Piergiorgio is a
    Cartesian. We agree about the historical facts. We only disagree
    about the emphasis. This book is Piergiorgio's version of the truth.
    My version would be slightly different.


    In the Cartesian version of twentieth-century mathematics,
    there were two decisive events. The first was the International
    Congress of Mathematicians in Paris in 1900, at which Hilbert
    gave the keynote address, charting the course of mathematics
    for the coming century by propounding his famous list of
    twenty-three outstanding unsolved problems. The second decisive
    event was the formation of the Bourbaki group of mathematicians
    in France in the 1930s, dedicated to publishing aseries of textbooks
    that would establish a unifYing framework for all of mathematics.
    The Hilbert problems were enormously successful in guiding mathematical
    research into fruitful directions. Some of them were solved and some
    remain unsolved,but almost all of them stimulated the growth of new ideas
    and new fields of mathematics. The Bourbaki project was equally
    influential. It changed the style of mathematics for the next
    fifty years, imposing a logical coherence that did not exist before,
    and moving the emphasis from concrete examples to abstract generalities.
    In the Bourbaki scheme of things, mathematics is the abstract structure
    included in the Bourbaki textbooks. What is not in the textbooks is not
    mathematics.Concrete examples, since they do not appear in the textbooks,
    are not mathematics. The Bourbaki program was the extreme
    expression of the Cartesian style of mathematics. It narrowed
    the scope of mathematics by excluding all the beautiful flowers
    that Baconian travelers might collect by the wayside. Fortunately,
    Piergiorgio is not an extreme Cartesian. He allows many concrete examples
    to appear in his book. He includes beautiful flowers such as sporadic
    finite groups and packings of spheres in Euclidean spaces. He even
    includes examples from applied as well as from pure mathematics.
    He describes the Fields Medals, which are awarded at the quadrennial
    International Congress of Mathematicians to people who solve concrete
    problems as well as to people who create new abstract ideas.


    For me, as a Baconian, the main thing missing in this book
    is the element of surprise. When I look at the history of mathematics,
    I see a succession of illogical jumps, improbable coincidences,
    jokes of nature. One of the most profound jokes of
    nature is the square root of -1 that the physicist Erwin Schr6dinger
    put into his wave equation in 1926. This is barely mentioned in
    Piergiorgio's discussion of quantum mechanics in his
    chapter 3, section 4. The Schr6dinger equation describes correctly
    everything we know about the behavior of atoms. It is
    the basis of all of chemistry and most of physics. And that
    square root of -1 means that nature works with complex numbers
    and not with real numbers. This discovery came as a complete surprise,
    to Schr6dinger as well as to everybody else. According to Schrbdinger,
    his fourteen-year-old girlfriend Itha Junger said to him at the time,
    "Hey, you never even thought when you began that so much sensible stuff
    would come out of it." All through the nineteenth century, mathematicians from
    Abel to RIemann and Weierstrass had been creating a magnificent theory
    offunctions of complex variables. They had discovered that the theory of
    functions became far deeper and more powerful when it was extended from real
    to complex numbers. But they always thought of complex numbers as an
    artificial construction, invented by human mathematicians as a useful
    and elegant abstraction from real life. It never entered their
    heads that this artificial number system that they had invented
    was in fact the ground on which atoms move. They never imagined that nature
    had got there first.

    Another joke of nature is the precise linearity of quantum
    mechanics, the fact that the possible states of any physical object
    form a linear space. Before quantum-mechanics was invented,
    classical physics was always nonlinear, and linear models were
    only approximately valid. After quantum mechanics,
    nature itself suddenly became linear. This had profound consequences
    for mathematics. During the nineteenth century, Sophus Lie developed
    his elaborate theory of continuous groups,intended to clarifY the
    behavior of classical dynamical systems. Lie groups were then oflittle
    interest either to mathematicians or to physicists. The nonlinear theory
    was too complicated for the mathematicians and too obscure for the physicists.
    Lie died a disappointed man. And then, fifty years later, it turned out
    that nature was precisely linear, and the theory oflinear representations
    of Lie algebras was the natural language of particle physics. Lie groups
    and Lie algebras were reborn as one of the central themes of twentieth-century
    mathematics, as discussed in Piergiorgio's chapter 2, section 12.


    A third joke of nature is the existence of quasi-crystals,
    briefly discussed by Piergiorgio at the beginning of his chapter
    3. In the nineteenth century, the study of crystals led to a complete
    enumeration of possible discrete symmetry-groups in Euclidean space.
    Theorems were proved, establishing the fact that in three-dimensional
    space discrete symmetry groups could contain only rotations of order
    three, four, or six. Then in 1984 quasi-crystals were discovered, real
    solid objects growing out ofliquid metal alloys, showing the symmetry of
    the icosahedral group which includes fivefold rotations. Meanwhile,
    the mathematician Roger Penrose had discovered the Penrose tilings of
    the plane. These are arrangements of parallelograms that cover
    a plane with pentagonal long-range order. The alloy quasi-crystals are
    three-dimensional analogs of the two-dimensional Penrose tilings.
    After these discoveries, mathematicians had to enlarge the theory of
    crystallographic groups so as to include quasi-crystals. That is a major
    program of research which is still in progress.


    I mention in conclusion one of my favorite Baconian dreams,
    the possible connection between the theory of one-dimensional
    quasi-crystals and the theory of the Riemann zeta-function.
    A one-dimensional quasi-crystal need not have any symmetry.
    It is defined simply as a non periodic arrangement of mass-points
    on a line whose Fourier transform is also an arrangement of mass-points
    on a line. Because of the lack of any requirement of symmetry, quasi-crystals
    have much greater freedom to exist in one dimension than in two or three.
    Almost nothing is known about the possible abundance of one-dimensional
    quasi-crystals. Likewise, not much is known about the
    zeros of the Riemann zeta-function, described by Piergiorgio
    in his chapter 5, section 2. The RIemann Hypothesis, the statement that
    all the zeros of the zeta-function with trivial exceptions lie on a certain
    straight line in the complex plane, was conjectured by Riemann in 1859.
    To prove it is the most famous unsolved problem in the whole of mathematics.
    One fact that we know is that, if the Riemann Hypothesis is true, then
    the zeta-function zeros on the critical line are a quasi-crystal
    according to the definition. If the RIemann Hypothesis is true,
    the zeta-function zeros have a Fourier transform consisting of
    mass-points at logarithms of all powers of prime integers and
    nowhere else. This suggests a possible approach to the proof
    of the Riemann Hypothesis. First you make a complete classification of
    all one-dimensional quasi-crystals, and write down a list of them.
    Collecting and classifYing new species of objects is a quintessentially
    Baconian activity. Then you look through the list and see whether the
    zeta-function zeros are there. If the zeta-function zeros are there,
    then you have proved the Riemann Hypothesis, and you need only wait for
    the next International Congress of Mathematicians to collect your Fields
    Medal. Of course the difficult part of this approach is collect-
    ing and classifYing the quasi-crystals. I leave that as an exercise
    for the reader.

    Freeman Dyson
    Institute for Advanced Study
    Princeton, New Jersey, USA

  • 相关阅读:
    JavasScript 实现二分法快排注意点
    JS的面向对象二(通过构造函数的方式)
    JS的面向对象一(通过构造函数的方式)
    leetcode.977_有序数组的平方
    leetcode_38.报数
    leetcode_20.c++有效的括号
    leetcode_21.c++合并两个有序列表
    leetcode_最长公共前缀
    T2_两数相加
    T1_两数之和
  • 原文地址:https://www.cnblogs.com/wangshixi12/p/9440454.html
Copyright © 2020-2023  润新知